Course Blog

These posts are in reverse-order, so the newest posts will always be at the top. The dates are when the post was first made.

Readings are in a restricted part of this site. The username and password for these will be announced in class and on Canvas.

Here is a sparser evolving index of all the handouts, webnotes and readings we’ve used during the course. Or you could look under the Canvas “Modules” tab.

Sun Mar 2

For Monday, I’m asking you to watch a video (linked in yesterday’s entry).

For Wednesday, read this article: Selections from Pereboom.

By the end of the week:

We may start to discuss this material on Wednesday, but if not should definitely get to it by Friday. The material in the blue box in the van Inwagen reading is stuff you can skim or skip for now; in a few weeks after we’ve introduced more of the debate, we’ll go back to this article and read and think about what’s in the blue box.

I may add some additional texts to this list; am thinking that through now.

Sat Mar 1

For Monday, watch this video by Victor Kumar (6 min) about “the problem of moral luck.” Here is a transcript of the video. (If you find the issues engaging, here is an optional longer discussion with Dana Nelkin (40 min, transcript), and here is an encyclopedia article by the same author.)

Also prepare your index cards saying what are the main idea(s) you will be presenting in your paper (what new arguments or objections or examples you’ll be advancing or responding to). You’ll be sharing these cards with your peers and asking each other questions about them.

Thu Feb 27

Some of you asked for help finding additional reading to help with your papers, especially regarding the Pairing Problem. Here is a selection from Jaegwon Kim’s textbook that discusses epiphenomenalism and most of our arguments against interactionism. (Not much on Conservation of Energy, though, but Gennaro discusses that.) It’s entirely optional to do any extra reading for the papers, but if you want to, that would be a good place to start.

Note that, as I’ve warned you several times in our discussions, different philosophers don’t always define terms exactly the same way. Some of these differences show up between terms as I’ve introduced them to you and as Kim uses them:

  1. I said that “dualism” leaves open what view you take about the relation between you (the person) and your soul. Kim sometimes characterizes “dualism” as committed to the specific view that you are identical to your soul; other times he characterizes it as committed to the specific view that you are identical to a combination (or “union”) of your soul and your body.
  1. I said that “epiphenomenalism” leaves open whether mental things (events, processes, states) can cause other mental things. Kim characterizes “epiphenomenalism” as committed to the specific view that they cannot.
  1. I said that “causal closure” says only that physical events that have any causal explanation will have a sufficient physical cause (a physical cause that would be enough by itself). This seems to be Kim’s official understanding too. But he sometimes writes in a way that makes it sound like “causal closure” already directly says that there are no soul causes of physical things:

    the physical domain is causally closed. What does this mean? Pick any physical event … and trace its causal ancestry or posterity as far as you would like; the principle of physical causal closure says this will never take you outside the physical domain.

    the closure principle is consistent with mind-body dualism … All it requires is that there be no injection of causal influence into the physical world from the outside, including Cartesian minds.

    Instead of will never and there be no, I think Kim should have written that there doesn’t need to be any non-physical causes (or effects).

Mon Feb 24

Here again are the lecture notes on Causal Arguments against Interactionist forms of Dualism.

There’s a quiz due Tuesday night.

updated Here are the instructions and prompts for your papers, which are due at the end of next week (Friday March 7). The topics for the paper were distributed in class (but are also printed at the end of the instructions handout). Choose a topic and start thinking about it so that we can break into groups and bounce ideas off of each other on Wednesday.

We’re going to start turning to issues about free will. Maybe I’ll be able to introduce this topic on Wednesday, else on Friday. Our initial reading will be:

I won’t expect everyone will have read that until Friday, but if you have time earlier in the week you can get started.

Fri Feb 21

Today we resumed our discussion of Huxley and started to discuss other theories, and worries about, how the mental and the physical causally interact. Here is the handout I distributed in class, for those of you who weren’t there in person. Here is a recording of today’s meeting.

Here are lecture notes on Causal Arguments against Interactionist forms of Dualism. We’ve only talked through some of this material in class; we’ll continue on Monday by discussing the “Pairing Problem” and the worries about “Too Many Causes.”

There is no new reading for Monday. But I’ll be distributing instructions for the midterm paper then, which will prompt you to explore these issues about mental causation that we started discussing with Huxley and are continuing with on Monday. So make sure you’re comfortable with the readings, what we’ve discussed in class, and my lecture notes. Ask questions (either in or outside of class) about any parts of the discussion you’re not tracking.

I can see that some of you are keeping up and others aren’t (at any rate, aren’t entirely). I’m happy to help you get back on track, if you’re slipping, but you’ll probably need to be putting in more effort — reading the texts and notes more than once, making annotations while you do so, formulating specific questions to ask me, and so on. But the longer you let yourself slip behind, the more challenging and overwhelming it may be to remedy.

We’ll discuss the details of the papers next week. You are going to need to work on them multiple sessions, and then turn in the best drafts you can, before spring break. Then I will give you feedback on these drafts, and you will also get some drafts of each others to provide peer feedback on. Then you will rewrite the papers in response to all the feedback, and your further thinking and planning. Both the initial drafts and the rewritten versions will be graded. For your course grade, I am only going to evaluate these papers for effort. But I will also tell you what grade they would have gotten if they were being evaluated for the quality of what you produced.

The best way for you to get strong marks for effort on these papers — as well as the best way for you to develop the skills that other parts of your course grade will be measuring — is to strive to produce the best quality paper you can. Both for the initial draft and for the rewrite.

On Wednesday (or perhaps Friday) of next week, we’ll start discussing Free Will. I’ll assign some initial readings on this on Monday. There will also be a (brief) quiz about the mental causation material, due Tuesday evening (or perhaps Thursday, if we need to continue discussing the issues into Wednesday).

Added: Niko said something at the end of class about “contrapositives” which makes me realize some clarifying remarks could be helpful.

  1. What we’re thinking about now are when some things can cause other things. This is not the same as an if-then relationship, though it will often be what explains why certain if-then relationships hold. But if-then relationships can hold for other reasons too.

  2. If there’s a fire, there will be smoke. Why? Because the fire will cause the smoke. (Fires don’t always cause smoke, but suppose we’re talking about a specific situation where they would.) If there’s smoke, there will be a fire behind it. Why? Again, because the fire causes the smoke. If fire fighters show up, an insurance claim will be submitted tomorrow. Why? Because a fire caused both things to happen. In all these examples, we have a relationship of if-P-then-Q, but sometimes P causes Q, sometimes Q causes P, sometimes they’re both caused by something else. Some if-then relationships don’t involve any causes: for example, if you light a fire inside this room, you will have broken the law. But lighting the fire doesn’t cause you to break the law, as a further effect. It already counts as breaking the law (given what the law prohibits).

  3. As I said, if one thing causes something else, often there will be a corresponding if-then relationship. (But sometimes not. We’ll discuss such tricky cases next week.) But if-then relationships aren’t the same thing as causal relationships. Contrapositives have to do with if-then relationships. “If P then Q” is equivalent to its contrapositive, “If not-Q then not-P.” But when P causes Q, we normally won’t want to say that the absence of Q also causes the absence of P. (My feeding the cat on Monday causes it to be alive on Tuesday; but its not being alive on Tuesday didn’t cause me not to feed it on Monday.)

  4. One way to ask about causes is to ask a Why? question, and one way to describe causes is to say Because… But be careful, because Why? and Because can mean other things too. If I say “Why is the cake baked?” one answer may be to tell me about the actions of the cook that caused the baking. But another answer may be to give you my evidence for thinking that the cake is baked — which might be that, for example, my neighbor promised to bake it before we get home tonight. “Because she promised” can justify my claim that the cake will be baked, but doesn’t have to be what motivated or caused the baking to happen. Another way to answer the question “Why is the cake baked?” may be to explain what we mean by “being baked.” (Perhaps there’s some non-standard methods of baking that you didn’t know about.) So don’t take it for granted that every time someone answers a Why? question, or correctly says “Because…,” they are describing a causal relation.

  5. What then does causing involve? This is a hard question, that much philosophical work has wrestled with. But some initial ideas are that some notions that are more familiar to us have a causal element to them. If you killed a cat, you caused it to die. If you baked a cake, you caused it to heat up for a period of time. The more general notion of causing is some kind of abstraction or generalization from notions like killing, and baking, and so on; and also from what physics tells us about how systems can/will evolve over time.

  6. In some examples, we talk about things or people being causes (as when I said you baked a cake), but many philosophers think that (perhaps sometimes? perhaps always?) this can be understood in terms of something you did, that is, some event you were part of, being the cause. (For example, it was you putting the dough in the oven and turning the knob that caused the cake to bake.) We’ll talk more in later weeks about whether causes should always fundamentally be understood as being events, in this way.

Mon Feb 17

As I said in email, class for Wednesday probably won’t be held in person, given the big storm they’re expecting. If the University doesn’t cancel classes outright, I’ll send you a Canvas announcement Wednesday morning saying explicitly whether we’ll be meeting by Zoom or in person.

We’ll continue to discuss the Huxley article on Wednesday. Here are some lecture notes on that article, covering what we talked about today and also things we’ll talk through on Wednesday.

Huxley is sort-of an example of what van Inwagen and other contemporary authors call “epiphenomenalist,” though Huxley doesn’t use that label himself. (I explain why I only say “sort-of” in the notes.)

If you want to read more about Descartes, or Huxley, or epiphenomenalism, there are some Wikipedia links.

For discussion on Wednesday and Friday, please read:

Regarding philosophical writing, we’ll talk about this many times over the coming weeks. But you may already find it helpful to read my Guidelines on Writing Philosophy. These are notes I put together (drawing from many sources) when I started teaching. They’ve since become widely used by other philosophy teachers too. I’ve also collected some useful pages of advice others have written. I’m still looking through these to figure out which do I think would be most helpful to give you as supplements.

Fri Feb 14

Read for Monday: Huxley. Also go back and re-read pp. 226–229 of the van Inwagen selection.

Thu Feb 13

Because our class time is short, our opportunities for group discussion are really valuable. It’s disappointing when we find time for them but some of you spend time on your devices instead of engaging in discussion with each other. As announced on the syllabus, participation and engagement with the course makes up 15% of your final course grade. If you participate here and there to a moderate extent, you’ll get a moderate grade for this, not a punishing one. But you are squandering an opportunity to get a strong grade that could help offset other grades for the course that will be more challenging — in addition to squandering opportunities to develop and exercise the skills that the class aims to teach, and will increasingly be drawing on.

The prompt for our in-class writing on Friday is:

First, choose some aspect of our mental lives or kind of mental state and make a case that it promises to be in principle more resistant to being understood as a physical process, explainable by science, than other phenomena like the life cycle of plants. So this part of our mental life should be a top candidate for requiring a non-physical soul. Given the time constraints of this exercise, you’re not expected to be able to go into much detail. But do aim not just to express an opinion, but also to point to some reasons for it. What other mental states in the neighborhood of that one should it be distinguished from, because they might be easier to understand as physical processes? What makes that mental state stand out as being especially hard for physical sciences to explain?

The second part of the exercise is to take the other side, and say what you think would be the most promising responses for someone who thinks the mental state you chose will eventually be explainable as a physical process, in the same way the life cycle of plants has been. Again, you are not expected to be able to go into details. But what can people who have this view say to justify their optimism?

Some of you may be genuinely undecided between these perspectives, and able to sympathetically occupy them each in turn. Others will already have a strong preference for one of the viewpoints. Even if you’re of the second sort, though, for this exercise try to articulate some ideas on behalf of both sides.

Here is some help mapping out van Inwagen’s discussion of the “second argument” for dualism, which is longer and more complex than any of the others.

So in the end, even though the physicalist is giving us less than we’d like, and still leaving things unsatisfyingly mysterious, arguably so too is the dualist. If van Inwagen is right, the considerations of this “second argument” don’t really end up giving us more reason to accept dualism.

Fri Feb 5

There is no class on Monday. For Wednesday, continue with the readings linked below (especially the van Inwagen). Here is one additional webnote to read:

As I mentioned in class, next week there will be a quiz due Thursday night. Also at some point in the next few classes, you will do some in-class writing addressing a prompt I bring to class.

Mon Feb 3

We’ll continue reading the van Inwagen selection over the next two weeks. For Wednesday, continue reading to the top of p. 233 (the end of his “first argument” for dualism). There are also some a few other readings for Wednesday. Each is short, but together they add up:

Remember there’s also a quiz due Tuesday night.

Looking ahead, we’ll be discussing the issues we’re reading about for Wednesday for a few classes; those and the remainder of the van Inwagen reading will be all that’s on our plate until the end of next week. You should continue reading rhe van Inwagen reading to the end as soon as you’re able to. As I said in class, his discussion of a “second argument” for dualism is complex and will take some special attention to follow. I encourage you to try to figure out the structure of that discussion on your own — even if you don’t figure out the details of what he thinks justifies each of the claims he makes. I will give you some input later about how I’d break it up into pieces, so you can compare your efforts to my suggestions. But you’ll learn better by first trying it on your own.

As I also said in class, don’t worry yet about van Inwagen’s discussion of “interactionism” and its alternatives like “epiphenomenalism.” We’ll come back and re-read those sections, and discuss the surrounding issues, later in February.

Those of you who missed class, I forwarded you the Zoom recording. I hope that the video and audio worked OK. Here is an annotated copy of the document I marked up in class today. Those who were in class might also want to look at that. After class, I filled in a few more annotations that there wasn’t time to mention in class. I made those in red so that it was visible which ones I made in class (in black pencil) and which ones I added later.

Fri Jan 31

Here is the page I promised about messiness in philosophy, as for example in the distinction between “abstract” and “concrete,” and in explaining what we mean when we argue about whether something “is a substance.”

I said there will be a quiz coming up soon. I’ll make it due Tuesday night.

For Monday’s class read this handout about reading philosophy articles. Also start reading this selection from Peter van Inwagen’s book Metaphysics. That whole PDF is long and complex, and we’ll be working through it over a couple of classes. For this first discussion, read up to the middle of p. 230. Also, if you haven’t started reading the Gennaro text yet, catch up by reading to p. 21.

When you come to class on Monday, bring either a printout of the van Inwagen text or a device where you can open a local copy of the PDF and annotate it.

Some remarks about the van Inwagen reading. Our thin textbooks like Gennaro’s may be clear and straightforward enough that you don’t need to work hard to understand the structure of their text. The ideas may be hard, but I hope it won’t be a challenge to follow these texts’ discussion of them. Other readings we look at in the course will demand more work from you as a reader. As philosophical writing goes, the van Inwagen reading should be clear and accessible to beginners in philosophy like yourselves. At least, individual sentences and paragraphs should be clear. But it will be a longer and more complex text than anaything we’ve looked at so far. So you should expect to spend some time working on understanding it. You should also expect to read it more than once. It won’t be enough to just get the big picture and overall feel of the text. You need to go through the reading carefully and understand the details. The “Reading Philosophy” webpage tries to give you some guidance about how to do that.

reading philosophy

Peter van Inwagen was an important metaphysician based at Syracuse and Notre Dame, but is now retired from teaching. (He still sometimes visits at Duke.)

Note that his family name is “van Inwagen.” Some people’s surnames/family names are made up of more than one word. For example, when you refer to the Colombian author Gabriel García Márquez, you don’t say “Márquez said so-and-so.” You refer to him as “García Márquez.” There are various and sometimes complicated histories of how people get compound surnames like this. Sometimes it’s the result of taking a compound name upon marriage (Kim Kardashian West). Sometimes it’s the result of the person’s parents keeping different surnames from each other. Sometimes the explanation lies several generations back (Helena Bonham Carter). In European-derived names, a common pattern is for surnames to begin with “von” (German) or “van” (Dutch) or variations on “de” (several Romance languages). These initial words are part of the surname. You don’t talk about the painters Gogh or Vinci, or the actors Niro or Sydow or Damme, or the director Palma. You talk about van Gogh, da Vinci, De Niro, von Sydow, Van Damme, and de Palma. Sometimes the person (or their parents or more distant ancestors) chose to capitalize the initial “De” or “Van,” other times not. In van Inwagen’s case, the “van” is not capitalized. (You can capitalize it at the start of a sentence.) If you’re going to refer to him, you should use his full name “Peter van Inwagen” or his surname, which is “van Inwagen.” Not “Inwagen” or “Vaninwagen.”

Mon Jan 27

Here is a writeup of some notes on animal cognition. We talked through some of this material on Friday and will continue doing so today.

Readings for Wednesday:

Thu Jan 23

I’ll post the grades from this week’s quizzes soon.

Tomorrow, we’ll continue discussing questions and interesting facts about what behavior animals display, and what mental states and processes and abilities that behavior may be evidence for.

As I said last week, for tomorrow, please read these two selections:

Here are some notes on these readings:

For the “Star Witness” reading, the “Reader Assignment” at the end is just part of the original text. It’s not a written assignment for our course. Also, the specific nature of the crime the parrot may be a witness to is not crucial to the story. For our purposes, neither do we need to sort out the legal issues discussed in the text, such as whether witnesses need to be cross-examinable. We’re reading and discussing this text just to get leverage on questions about what cognitive abilities it’s reasonable to think a parrot might have, and why.

The Leiber textbook is one of the three you need to purchase for the course: it’s available in the bookstore, or you can find links on the front webpage There’s part of this reading selection that I think is more complicated than it needs to be. Here’s some context and explanation to help you track what’s going on:

One of the people taking part in that dialogue is named Mary Godwin. Some back-history: William Godwin and Mary Wollstonecraft were philosophers in late 1700s. They had a daughter Mary Godwin (Mary Wollstonecraft then died shortly after childbirth) who grew up, got involved with the poet Shelley and wrote Franksentein. The mother was born with the name Wollstonecraft but took her husband’s name Godwin on marriage; the daughter was born with the name Godwin but took Shelley’s name when she eventually married him. The dialogue refers to the mother as “Mary Godwin” and it’s a story about her that’s discussed in the first chapter.

Thomas Paine wrote The Rights of Man in 1791, arguing (in defense of the French Revolution) that all citizens (not just aristocrats) had “natural rights,” and that they can/should revolt when their government doesn’t protect these rights. Paine also argued for education and welfare reforms. Around the same time, Mary Wollstonecraft Godwin (that is, the mother) wrote A Vindication of the Rights of Woman, arguing that women deserved “rational education” (versus just “domestic education”), and that they had the same natural rights as men.

Thomas Taylor then wrote A Vindication of the Rights of Brutes in 1792; this was meant to be a satire of Paine’s and Godwin’s arguments. The absurdity of counting animals as persons was meant to imply it was also absurd to count poor servants and women as equals to their superiors.

The dialogue invokes this historical exchange for several purposes: (1) to remind us that Paine and (the historical) Godwin had to argue that all men, and women, deserved the same rights as others — it took work to overcome people’s doubts about this; (2) to remind us that the arguments Paine and Godwin offered had to do with reason and intelligence, which as Taylor observed, are present to some degree in animals too; (3) the (future, in-the-book) Godwin agrees with Taylor that there’s a “slippery slope” from the arguments of Paine and (the historical) Godwin to accepting that animals also have rights. Taylor thought therefore those arguments must be wrong (hence his satire). The future Godwin instead endorses the arguments and this further conclusion.

Fri Jan 17

Here is a recording of today’s class (passcode &YsG40Y?).

Here are some lecture notes:

We only got through some of the material on the first, and none of the material on the second. But have a look at these notes both for review and to prepare you for class summary of the rest on Wedneday. On Wednesday, we’ll also start to dicuss how to map the “outer” phenomena of behavior and speech, and what we learned about which of these various animals exhibit.

There is a quiz posted, due by Tuesday night, which invites you to share some of what you’ve read about animal abilities. The quiz also asks about the contrast between episodic and standing mental phenomena, which we discussed in class on Friday. (See the recording if you missed this or need a refresher.) This contrast isn’t a focus of the lecture notes linked above.

For Wednesday, there is no additional reading. But before next Friday’s class (Jan 26), please read these selections:

Sun Jan 12

Here is a page of links to articles and videos about animal minds.

As I said yesterday, I don’t expect anyone to try to read/watch all of these. But I do ask you to make a good faith effort to spend time browsing some of them, and/or the selection from the Dr Dolittle’s Delusion book, or doing your own research, before Friday’s class. I will be inviting you to summarize and react to some of what you learn.

Sat Jan 11

That was a great discussion of “mother” yesterday. This is like the wax on/wax off training in Karate Kid. The shape of things we said about the concept “mother” will come up again for the concepts mind/self/I/point-of-view, on the one hand, and the concepts of being free/having a choice/things being up to you, on the other.

For Monday, continue reading the pages linked to on Wednesday. I already mentioned that the “Glossary” page from those links isn’t important for now, also the “Conditionals” page is one that we’re going to spend more time on later, so do read that page now, but don’t worry if the details aren’t entirely clear to you yet.

Come to class with questions. The review lists from some of those pages are reproduced on (the front side of) the last page of yeterday’s handouts. There are also some exercises on the handout; think about them and we’ll talk them through.

The back side of the last page of the handout has some passages on it (taken from the readings) that “look argumentative,” but don’t count as having arguments in the philosopher’s sense, or at any rate, no good arguments. An exercise we’re going to do in class is break into groups, each group chooses two passages and comes up with ways to add in more premises/claims so that the result does look more like an argument. (It doesn’t have to be an argument you agree with!) Give some thought to which passages you can imagine some natural ways to do this for. We’ll do this exercise after we get through questions/discussions about the readings. It might be on Monday, or perhaps on Wednesday.

After we finish working through these preparatory readings, we’re going to take up our first main topic, that of animal mentality or cognition. We’ll get to some philosophical readings on this. (I have them on the Calendar for Fri Jan 24, but we may end up adjusting that.) Before we do that, it will be helpful for you to learn about surprising things that some animals can do, and things they can’t do. I said already, the exact details here aren’t going to matter so much for our discussion. But it still will be helpful to have a rough feel for the details. There are different ways to do this. I have a long selection from one book that talks about animal cognition in general, and their linguistic abilities and limitations in particular. That’s here:

That pdf looks long, but if you go through it there’s a lot of partial pages. It looks to me to sum up to about 85 pages altogether. I think it’s a useful overview of the kind of information we want to be drawing on. But as I said, we don’t need to master the exact details. Alternatively, another thing you could do is browse through videos and popular science news articles showing off this or that surprising animal ability. I have some collections of these; I’ll try to curate a list of them for you over the next days. You can also search on your own on YouTube or Google for keywords like “animal cognition” or “intelligent animals.”

I put the Dr Dolittle reading on the calendar to read before our class next Friday, Jan 17, but I don’t mind if you want to instead spend your prep time watching/reading the other links I provide, or searching on your own. I don’t expect you to do all of these. And I don’t mind if some of you read through the whole Dr Dolittle selection quickly, and others get interested in some of the details in one section and read there more closely, never making it through the whole text. For this initial reading about animal minds, I’m just going to trust that you’ll each put in good faith efforts to read/watch/learn some more about the surprising things some animals can and cannot do. We can share highlights with each other in class.

Our later reading assignments won’t be so free-form as this. We’ll generally all want to be looking and talking about the same texts. But this seems to me a useful and interesting way to start off.

Wed Jan 8

Our first class meeting is on Wed Jan 8 (today). I’ll introduce you to our course topics and to what philosophical activity looks like.

There is no reading assigned before that meeting. But there is a substantial chunk of reading you should do afterwards, and be ready to discuss/ask questions about in our subsequent meetings. That is the group of web pages at this link:

(The last of those pages is a Glossary that I hope will be useful but is less important than the earlier pages.) Also this brief selection:

(Pages with a “restricted” URL like that one need a username/password, which will be announced in class and on Canvas. You should only need to enter it once per device.)

Those pages already have developed explanations of the relevant concepts, and I’m not planning to repeat/summarize those in class. But I will take questions about the material on Friday and Monday, and we’ll talk through the Review lists at the end of the pages. Come to class with ideas about what you find confusing or would be helpful to explore further.